5X5 Episode 56: Difference between revisions
m (updated '5x5 editing required') |
(Proof-read and tick) |
||
(One intermediate revision by one other user not shown) | |||
Line 1: | Line 1: | ||
{{ | {{Template:5X5 infobox | ||
| | |verified = y | ||
| | |episodeID = 5X5 Episode 56 | ||
| | |Contents = Probability | ||
|episodeDate = 4<sup>th</sup> February 2009 | |||
|rebecca = y | |||
|bob = y | |||
|jay = y | |||
|evan = y | |||
|downloadLink = http://media.libsyn.com/media/sgu5x5/SGU5x52009-02-04.mp3 | |||
|notesLink = http://www.theskepticsguide.org/archive/podcastinfo.aspx?mid=2&pid=56 | |||
|forumLink = http://sguforums.com/index.php/topic,18270.0.html | |||
|}} | |}} | ||
== Probability == | |||
{{5x5intro}} | {{5x5intro}} | ||
S: This is the SGU 5X5 and tonight we're talking about | S: This is the SGU 5X5 and tonight we're talking about {{w|Probability|probability}}. | ||
E : Probably. | E: Probably. | ||
S: Probably. Not ''probably'' but ''probability''. Mathematical probability is something that humans have an inherently a poor understanding of. We do not have a good mind for numbers or an intuitive sense of probability, especially when you start dealing with large numbers, and this causes people to form erroneous conclusions all the time. | S: Probably. Not ''probably'' but ''probability''. Mathematical probability is something that humans have an inherently a poor understanding of. We do not have a good mind for numbers or an intuitive sense of probability, especially when you start dealing with large numbers, and this causes people to form erroneous conclusions all the time. | ||
R: Yeah, my favorite example of how we can't really understand probability is the example that if you have twenty-three people in a room together, what are the chances that two of them share a birthday? And a lot of people would think that the chances are very small when in fact they're greater than 50%. It's one of those things where, you know, it doesn't make sense at first but when you examine the | R: Yeah, my favorite example of how we can't really understand probability is the example that if you have twenty-three people in a room together, what are the chances that two of them share a birthday? And a lot of people would think that the chances are very small when in fact they're greater than 50%. It's one of those things where, you know, it doesn't make sense at first but when you examine the {{w|Birthday problem|math behind it}}, it makes perfect sense. Our intuition kind of leads us astray in that case. | ||
E: Another example pertaining to the law of very large numbers and probability is that of lottery winners. You would think that the odds of a person winning a lottery jackpot twice in their lifetime would be something astronomical, maybe in the hundreds of millions, billions or trillions. But in actuality, the odds of a person winning two lottery jackpots is about one in thirty. The point there is to remember is that, yeah, the odds of me, Evan, winning two jackpots in my lifetime is probably in the trillions but the odds of somebody, anybody, of all the people who play lottery, of all the people who have | E: Another example pertaining to the law of very large numbers and probability is that of lottery winners. You would think that the odds of a person winning a lottery jackpot twice in their lifetime would be something astronomical, maybe in the hundreds of millions, billions or trillions. But in actuality, the odds of a person winning two lottery jackpots is about one in thirty. The point there is—to remember is that, yeah, the odds of me, Evan, winning two jackpots in my lifetime is probably in the trillions but the odds of somebody, anybody, of all the people who play lottery, of all the people who have the possibility of buying lottery tickets, that whittles down to a small number, which is just one in thirty. | ||
B: That's a good point, Evan. It's called the | B: That's a good point, Evan. It's called the {{w|Law of truly large numbers|law of truly large numbers}}. It's a very important aspect of probability and statistics. Basically, this law says that truly bizarre coincidences are bound to happen when sample sizes get big enough, such as the millions of people playing lotto numbers. One of my favorite example is if you dream about a plane crash the night before a real one happens, you might think, "wow this must be precognition; I might be psychic," but consider that six billion people were dreaming last night, and probably a million of them all could have had dreams of plane crashes. Just from this law of truly large numbers, it's just bound to happen when you've got a sample size that is just so huge. | ||
S: That's right. In the city of ten million people, a one in ten million coincidence happen every day. | S: That's right. In the city of ten million people, a one-in-ten-million coincidence happen every day. | ||
R: So you should never tell somebody that they're one in a million because frankly that's insulting them. | R: So you should never tell somebody that they're one in a million because, frankly, that's insulting them. | ||
B/E: ''(laughs)'' | |||
S: That's right. | S: That's right. | ||
Line 41: | Line 37: | ||
E: It depends on where you live. | E: It depends on where you live. | ||
J: And this adding more proof to the fact that psychics don't exist because statistically some psychic should have guessed that 9-11 was going to happen and that didn't even happen. | J: And this adding more proof to the fact that psychics don't exist because, statistically, some psychic should have guessed that 9-11 was going to happen and that didn't even happen. | ||
S: And speaking of psychics, they depend upon poor intuitive sense of probability when they do their | S: And speaking of psychics, they depend upon poor intuitive sense of probability when they do their {{w|Cold reading|cold readings}}, 'cause they'll throw out a lot of guesses and some of them will hit and they'll count on the reader, the person being read, not only remembering the hits and forgetting the misses but grossly underestimating the probability that they would have gotten a few of those guesses correct by chance alone. | ||
To follow up on the lottery example, Bob, that was a very very good example | To follow up on the lottery example, Bob, that was a very, very good example; I think it's one that people can relate to... and also specifically, the difference between John Smith winning and the difference between just someone somewhere winning. In fact, this comes up a lot, for example, when creationists talk about the incredible improbability of evolution, they're making the lottery fallacy<ref>Neurologica Blog: [http://theness.com/neurologicablog/index.php/biocentrism-pseudoscience/ Biocentrism Pseudoscience]</ref>, the probability fallacy. They're assuming the probability of life as it exists now occurring by chance. Yes, that's very unlikely. Specific things evolving may be inherently unlikely, but the fact that ''something'' evolved is not unlikely at all. It's guaranteed, just as it's guaranteed that eventually someone's going to win the lottery. | ||
{{5x5outro}} | |||
==References== | |||
<references/> | |||
{{5X5 Navigation}} | {{5X5 Navigation}} | ||
{{5X5 categories | |||
|General Science = y | |||
|Logic & Philosophy = y | |||
}} |
Latest revision as of 01:13, 21 July 2013
5X5 Episode 56 | |
---|---|
Probability | |
4th February 2009 | |
5X5 55 | 5X5 57 |
Skeptical Rogues | |
S: Steven Novella | |
R: Rebecca Watson | |
B: Bob Novella | |
J: Jay Novella | |
E: Evan Bernstein | |
Links | |
Download Podcast | |
Show Notes | |
Forum Topic |
Probability[edit]
Voice-over: You're listening to the Skeptics' Guide 5x5, five minutes with five skeptics, with Steve, Jay, Rebecca, Bob and Evan.
S: This is the SGU 5X5 and tonight we're talking about probability.
E: Probably.
S: Probably. Not probably but probability. Mathematical probability is something that humans have an inherently a poor understanding of. We do not have a good mind for numbers or an intuitive sense of probability, especially when you start dealing with large numbers, and this causes people to form erroneous conclusions all the time.
R: Yeah, my favorite example of how we can't really understand probability is the example that if you have twenty-three people in a room together, what are the chances that two of them share a birthday? And a lot of people would think that the chances are very small when in fact they're greater than 50%. It's one of those things where, you know, it doesn't make sense at first but when you examine the math behind it, it makes perfect sense. Our intuition kind of leads us astray in that case.
E: Another example pertaining to the law of very large numbers and probability is that of lottery winners. You would think that the odds of a person winning a lottery jackpot twice in their lifetime would be something astronomical, maybe in the hundreds of millions, billions or trillions. But in actuality, the odds of a person winning two lottery jackpots is about one in thirty. The point there is—to remember is that, yeah, the odds of me, Evan, winning two jackpots in my lifetime is probably in the trillions but the odds of somebody, anybody, of all the people who play lottery, of all the people who have the possibility of buying lottery tickets, that whittles down to a small number, which is just one in thirty.
B: That's a good point, Evan. It's called the law of truly large numbers. It's a very important aspect of probability and statistics. Basically, this law says that truly bizarre coincidences are bound to happen when sample sizes get big enough, such as the millions of people playing lotto numbers. One of my favorite example is if you dream about a plane crash the night before a real one happens, you might think, "wow this must be precognition; I might be psychic," but consider that six billion people were dreaming last night, and probably a million of them all could have had dreams of plane crashes. Just from this law of truly large numbers, it's just bound to happen when you've got a sample size that is just so huge.
S: That's right. In the city of ten million people, a one-in-ten-million coincidence happen every day.
R: So you should never tell somebody that they're one in a million because, frankly, that's insulting them.
B/E: (laughs)
S: That's right.
E: It depends on where you live.
J: And this adding more proof to the fact that psychics don't exist because, statistically, some psychic should have guessed that 9-11 was going to happen and that didn't even happen.
S: And speaking of psychics, they depend upon poor intuitive sense of probability when they do their cold readings, 'cause they'll throw out a lot of guesses and some of them will hit and they'll count on the reader, the person being read, not only remembering the hits and forgetting the misses but grossly underestimating the probability that they would have gotten a few of those guesses correct by chance alone.
To follow up on the lottery example, Bob, that was a very, very good example; I think it's one that people can relate to... and also specifically, the difference between John Smith winning and the difference between just someone somewhere winning. In fact, this comes up a lot, for example, when creationists talk about the incredible improbability of evolution, they're making the lottery fallacy[1], the probability fallacy. They're assuming the probability of life as it exists now occurring by chance. Yes, that's very unlikely. Specific things evolving may be inherently unlikely, but the fact that something evolved is not unlikely at all. It's guaranteed, just as it's guaranteed that eventually someone's going to win the lottery.
S: SGU 5x5 is a companion podcast to the Skeptics' Guide to the Universe, a weekly science podcast brought to you by the New England Skeptical Society in association with skepchick.org. For more information on this and other episodes, visit our website at www.theskepticsguide.org. Music is provided by Jake Wilson.
References[edit]
- ↑ Neurologica Blog: Biocentrism Pseudoscience